Page images
PDF
EPUB

15452:36 15447.80

The Gift of

Mrs. Ezra Abbot,

of Cambridge,

Jan. 21, 1885.

8221

INTRODUCTORY.

THE Essay on Man consists of four Epistles addressed to Lord Bolingbroke. It is but a portion of a large poem contemplated, but not completed. Hence the title imperfectly describes its contents. It is less a treatise on Man than on the moral order of the world of which man is a part. The Essay is a vindication of Providence. The appearances of evil in the world arise from our seeing only a part of the whole. Excesses and contrary qualities are means by which the harmony of the system is procured. The ends of Providence are answered even by our errors and imperfections. God designs happiness to be equal, but realises it through general laws. Virtue only constitutes a happiness which is universally attainable. This happiness through virtue is only reached in society, or social order, which is only a part of the general order. The perfection of virtue is a conformity to the order of Providence here crowned by the hope of full satisfaction hereafter.

The argument of the Essay on Man is said by Johnson, Lives of the Poets, Pope, to have been supplied to Pope by Bolingbroke. Johnson relied on a statement made by Joseph Warton, Genius and Writings of Pope, 2. 58, that Lord Bathurst (died 1777) had repeatedly assured him that he had read the whole scheme of the poem in the handwriting of Bolingbroke, and that Pope did no more than put it into verse. See Boswell; Life of Johnson, Letter 355. Lord Bathurst, however, was either mistaken or was misunderstood. It is possible that what Lord Bathurst saw were the Fragments or Minutes of Essays, now included in Lord Bolingbroke's printed Works. These Fragments were occasional scraps

communicated to Pope as they were written. Single passages in these Fragments resemble passages in Pope's Essay. But even if the communication of the Fragments preceded the composition of the Essay on Man, they are far from containing the whole scheme of the Poem. Both the Essay on Man and Bolingbroke's Minutes derive their colouring from a common source.

The Essay on Man was composed at a time when the reading public in this country were occupied with an intense and eager curiosity by speculation on the first principles of Natural Religion. Everywhere, in the pulpit, in the coffee-houses, in every pamphlet, argument on the origin of evil, on the goodness of God, and the constitution of the world, was rife. Into the prevailing topic of polite conversation Bolingbroke, who returned from exile in 1723, was drawn by the bent of his native genius. Pope followed the example and impulse of his friend's more powerful mind. Thus much there was of special suggestion. But the arguments or topics of the poem are to be traced to books in much vogue at the time; to Shaftesbury's Characteristics (1711), King On the Origin of Evil (1702), and particularly to Leibnitz, Essais de Théodicée (1710). Pope's ambition as a poet led him to take up a subject which involved abstract considerations for which he had no aptitude. He had hitherto only treated social or personal themes. Unless he was to be content to be read merely by 'the town,' he must apply himself to the larger argument which absorbed the attention of all serious minds. No writer, who desires to be read by his contemporaries, can neglect the topics in which his contemporaries feel a paramount interest. Pope brooded many years over the scheme of an ethical work. The First Part, or Epistle, was published, anonymously, in 1732. The Fourth Part came out, with his name, in 1734. He never completed any more of the work; though in 1738 he had not relinquished the project of a continuation, as we see from the Epilogue to the Satires 2. 255

[ocr errors]

Alas, alas! pray end what you began,

And write next winter more Essays on Man.'

In selecting his subject Pope was thus determined, against the bent of his own genius, by the direction in which the curiosity of his reading public happened to be exerted. Herein lay, to begin with, a source of weakness. To write on a thesis set by circumstances is to begin by wanting inspiration, which proceeds from the fullness of the heart. But when the thesis prescribed is also one which lies beyond the scope of the mental habits of the writer, the difficulties to be overcome are great indeed. The feeblest of Boileau's poems is his Epitre sur l'amour de Dieu, which he was drawn in to write because the Quietist controversy, in which he had no interest, was raging at court.

The subject of the Essay on Man is not, considered in itself, one unfit for poetry. Had Pope had a genius for philosophy, there was no reason why he should not have selected a philosophical subject. Didactic poetry is a mistake, if not a contradiction in terms. But poetry is not necessarily didactic because its subject is philosophical. And the highest phase of the philosophical imagination is tentative, not dogmatic. Philosophy cannot be presented as a system of truths for defence or proof. It offers considerations for meditation, and not fixed verities. It is an attempt to elevate the whole mind towards the contemplation of the phænomena of the world from their ideal side. Hence there is a close affinity between the mental state of the philosopher and the poet. Plato's Dialogues, though not in verse, address the same faculty of imagination to which poetry appeals. Poetry, philosophy, and art, in their highest condition, are one. The possibility of presenting the Christian ideas in a poetical garb had been shewn by Milton. There seems no reason why those of natural religion should not be offered for contemplation in a suitable form. We may adopt the words in which Madame d'Epinay rebuked the cynicism of Saint-Lambert: 'Vous, monsieur, qui êtes poëte, vous conviendrez avec moi que l'existence d'un Être éternel, tout puissant, souverainement intelligent, est le germe d'un plus bel enthousiasme.’

But it is not enough that a given subject should be in itself adapted for poetry; the poet who undertakes it should be in

« PreviousContinue »