Page images
PDF
EPUB

WE

CHAPTER II

DISCOVERY OF THE LAW OF REFRACTION.

E have seen in the former part of this history that the Greeks had formed a tolerably clear conception of the refraction as well as the reflection of the rays of light; and that Ptolemy had measured the amount of refraction of glass and water at various angles. If we give the names of the angle of incidence and the angle of refraction respectively to the angles which a ray of light makes with the line perpendicular to surface of glass or water (or any other medium) within and without the medium, Ptolemy had observed that the angle of refraction is always less than the angle of incidence. He had supposed it to be less in a given proportion, but this opinion is false; and was afterwards rightly denied by the Arabian mathematician Alhazen. The optical views which occur in the work of Alhazen are far sounder than those of his predecessors; and the book may be regarded as the most considerable monument which we have of the scientific genius of the Arabians; for it appears, for the most part, not to be borrowed from Greek authorities. The author not only asserts (lib. vii.), that refraction takes place towards the perpendicular, and refers to experiment for the truth of this: and that the quantities of the refraction differ according to the magnitudes of the angles which the directions of the incidental rays (primæ lineæ) make with the perpendiculars to the surface; but he also says distinctly and decidedly that the angles of refraction do not follow the proportion of the angles of incidence.

[2nd Ed.] [There appears to be good ground to assent to the assertion of Alhazen's originality, made by his editor Risner, who says, "Euclideum hic vel Ptolemaicum nihil fere est." Besides the doctrine of reflection and refraction of light, the Arabian author gives a description of the eye. He distinguishes three fluids, humor aqueus, crystallinus, vitreus, and four coats of the eye, tunica adherens, cornea, uvea, tunica reti similis. He distinguishes also three kinds of vision: "Visibile percipitur aut solo visu, aut visu et syllogismo, aut visu et anticipatâ notione." He has several propositions relating to what we sometimes call the Philosophy of Vision: for instance this: “E visi bili sæpius viso remanet in anima generalis notio," &c.]

The assertion, that the angles of refraction are not proportional to the angles of incidence, was an important remark; and if it had been steadily kept in mind, the next thing to be done with regard to refraction was to go on experimenting and conjecturing till the true law of refraction was discovered; and in the mean time to apply the principle as far as it was known. Alhazen, though he gives directions for making experimental measures of refraction, does not give any Table of the results of such experiments, as Ptolemy had done. Vitello, a Pole, who in the 13th century published an extensive work upon Optics, does give such a table; and asserts it to be deduced from experiment, as I have already said (vol. i.). But this assertion is still liable to doubt in consequence of the table containing impossible observations.

[2nd Ed.] [As I have already stated, Vitello asserts that his Tables were derived from his own observations. Their near agreement with those of Ptolemy does not make this improbable: for where the observations were only made to half a degree, there was not much room for observers to differ. It is not unlikely that the observations of refraction out of air into water and glass, and out of water into glass, were actually made; while the impossible values which accompany them, of the refraction out of water and glass into air, and out of glass into water, were calculated, and calculated from an erroneous rule.]

The principle that a ray refracted in glass or water is turned towards the perpendicular, without knowing the exact law of refraction, enabled mathematicians to trace the effects of transparent bodies in various cases. Thus in Roger Bacon's works we find a tolerably distinct explanation of the effect of a convex glass; and in the work of Vitello the effect of refraction at the two surfaces of a glass globe is clearly traceable.

Notwithstanding Alhazen's assertion of the contrary, the opinion was still current among mathematicians that the angle of refraction was proportional to the angle of incidence. But when Kepler's attention was drawn to the subject, he saw that this was plainly inconsistent with the observations of Vitello for large angles; and he convinced himself by his own experiments that the true law was something different from the one commonly supposed. The discovery of this true law excited in him an eager curiosity; and this point had the more interest for him in consequence of the introduction of a correction for atmospheric refraction into astronomical calculations, which had been made by Tycho, and of the invention of the telescope. In

his Supplement to Vitello, published in 1604, Kepler attempts to reduce to a rule the measured quantities of refraction. The reader who recollects what we have already narrated, the manner in which Kepler attempted to reduce to law the astronomical observations of Tycho,-devising an almost endless variety of possible formulæ, tracing their consequences with undaunted industry, and relating, with a vivacious garrulity, his disappointments and his hopes,-will not be surprised to find that he proceeded in the same manner with regard to the Tables of Observed Refractions. He tried a variety of constructions by triangles, conic sections, &c., without being able to satisfy himself; and he at last is obliged to content himself with an approximate rule, which makes the refraction partly proportional to the angle of incidence, and partly, to the secant of that angle. In this way he satisfies the observed refractions within a difference of less than half a degree each way. When we consider how simple the law of refraction is, (that the ratio of the sines of the angles of incidence and refraction is constant for the same medium,) it appears strange that a person attempting to discover it, and drawing triangles for the purpose, should fail; but this lot of missing what afterwards seems to have been obvious, is a common one in the pursuit of truth.

The person who did discover the Law of the Sines, was Willebrord Snell, about 1621; but the law was first published by Descartes, who had seen Snell's papers. Descartes does not acknowledge this law to have been first detected by another; and after his manner, instead of establishing its reality by reference to experiment, he pretends to prove à priori that it must be true,' comparing, for this purpose, the particles of light to balls striking a substance which accelerates them.

[2nd Ed.] [Huyghens says of Snell's papers, "Quæ et nos vidimus aliquando, et Cartesium quoque vidisse accepimus, et hinc fortasse mensuram illam quæ in sinibus consistit elicuerit." Isaac Vossius, De Lucis Naturâ et Proprietate, says that he also had seen this law in Snell's unpublished optical Treatise. The same writer says, "Quod itaque (Cartesius) habet, refractionum momenta non exigenda esse ad angulos sed ad lineas, id tuo Snellio, acceptum ferre debuisset, cujus

nomen more solito dissimulavit." "Cartesius got his law from Snell, and in his usual way, concealed it."

'L. U. K. Life of Kepler, p. 115.

Huyghens, Dioptrica, p. 2.

' Diopt. p. 53.

Huyghens' assertion, that Snell did not attend to the proportion of the sines, is very captious; and becomes absurdly so, when it is made to mean that Snell did not know the law of the sines. It is not denied that Snell knew the true law, or that the true law is the law of the sines. Snell does not use the trigonometrical term sine, but he expresses the law in a geometrical form more simply. Even if he had attended to the law of the sines, he might reasonably have preferred his own way of stating it.

James Gregory also independently discovered the true law of refraction; and, in publishing it, states that he had learnt that it had already been published by Descartes].

But though Descartes does not, in this instance, produce any good claims to the character of an inductive philosopher, he showed considerable skill in tracing the consequences of the principle when once adopted. In particular we must consider him as the genuine author of the explanation of the rainbow. It is true that Fleischer and Kepler had previously ascribed this phenomenon to the rays of sunlight which, falling on drops of rain, are refracted into each drop, reflected at its inner surface, and refracted out again: Antonio de Dominis had found that a glass globe of water, when placed in a particular position with respect to the eye, exhibited bright colors; and had hence explained the circular form of the bow, which, indeed, Aristotle had done before. But none of these writers had shown why there was a narrow bright circle of a definite diameter; for the drops which send rays to the eye after two refractions and a reflection, occupy a much wider space in the heavens. Descartes assigned the reason for this in the most satisfactory manner, by showing that the rays which, after two refractions and a reflection, come to the eye at an angle of about forty-one degrees with their original direction, are far more dense than those in any other position. He showed, in the same manner, that the existence and position of the secondary bow resulted from the same. laws. This is the complete and adequate account of the state of things, so far as the brightness of the bows only is concerned; the explanation of the colors belongs to the next article of our survey.

The explanation of the rainbow and of its magnitude, afforded by Snell's law of sines, was perhaps one of the leading points in the verification of the law. The principle, being once established, was applied, by the aid of mathematical reasoning, to atmospheric refractions, opti

[merged small][merged small][ocr errors][merged small]

cal instruments, diacaustic curves, (that is, the curves of intense light produced by refraction,) and to various other cases; and was, of course, tested and confirmed by such applications. It was, however, impossible to pursue these applications far, without a due knowledge of the laws by which, in such cases, colors are produced. To these we now proceed.

[2nd Ed.] [I have omitted many interesting parts of the history of Optics about this period, because I was concerned with the inductive discovery of laws, rather than with mathematical deductions from such laws when established, or applications of them in the form of instruments. I might otherwise have noticed the discovery of Spectacle Glasses, of the Telescope, of the Microscope, of the Camera Obscura, and the mathematical explanation of these and other phenomena, as given by Kepler and others. I might also have noticed the progress of knowledge respecting the Eye and Vision. We have seen that Alhazen described the structure of the eye. The operation of the parts was gradually made out. Baptista Porta compares the eye to his Camera Obscura (Magia Naturalis, 1579). Scheiner, in his Oculus, published 1652, completed the Theory of the Eye. And Kepler discussed some of the questions even now often agitated; as the causes and conditions of our seeing objects single with two eyes, and erect with inverted images.]

CHAPTER III.

DISCOVERY OF THE LAW OF DISPERSION BY REFRACTION.

MARLY attempts were made to account for the colors of the rain

EARLY

bow, and various other phenomena in which colors are seen to arise from transient and unsubstantial combinations of media. Thus Aristotle explains the colors of the rainbow by supposing' that it is light seen through a dark medium: "Now," says he, "the bright seen through the dark appears red, as, for instance, the fire of green wood seen through the smoke, and the sun through mist. Also the weaker is the light, or the visual power, and the nearer the color approaches to the black; becoming first red, then green, then purple. But the

Meteor. iii. 3, p. 373.

2 Ib. p. 374.

Ib. p. 375.

« PreviousContinue »